Centers for Disease Control and Prevention
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention CDC Home Search CDC CDC Health Topics A-Z    
Office of Genomics and Disease Prevention  
Office of Genomics and Disease Prevention

 

 Journal Publication

This paper was published with modifications in Epidemiol Rev 2000;22:169-175


Ethics in Epidemiology at the End of the Twentieth Century:  Ethics, Values, and Mission Statements

by Steven S. Coughlin

From the Epidemiology and Health Services Research Branch, Division of Cancer Prevention and Control, National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Centers for Disease Control and Prevention

Abbreviations: AIDS, CDC, DNA

Address for correspondence: Steven S. Coughlin, Ph.D., Epidemiology and Health Services Research Branch, Division of Cancer Prevention and Control, National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, 4770 Buford Highway, NE (K-55), Atlanta, GA 30341. E-mail sic9@cdc.gov

Running head: Ethics and Values in Epidemiology


bullet Introduction
bullet Core Values in Epidemiology
bullet Epidemiologic values reflected in mission statements
bullet Epidemiologic values reflected in ethics guidelines
bullet Epidemiologic values reflected in results from ethics surveys
bullet Professional Values and Epidemiology's Commitment to Public Health
bullet Ethics, Values, and Future Directions in Epidemiology
bullet References
bullet Table 1

Introduction

Important advances have occurred in ethics and epidemiology in the closing decades of the twentieth century (1, 2). These advances include explications of the societal importance of epidemiologic research and practice, clarifications of the ethical duties of epidemiologists, and the increasing integration of ethics into the professional life of epidemiologists (3-12). These developments in ethics are not isolated events. Rather, they have occurred in conjunction with historical events--improvements in institutional and regulatory safeguards for protecting human subjects, rising public concern over the privacy and confidentiality of medical records, the onset of the acquired immunodeficiency syndrome (AIDS) epidemic, and the emergence of molecular epidemiology, to name a few.

One sign of the increased attention to ethics and values in epidemiology in recent years is the development of ethics guidelines for epidemiologists and policy statements on data sharing, privacy and confidentiality protection, deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) testing for disease susceptibility, and other issues (6-10, 13-15). Courses on ethics in epidemiology and public health have also been initiated at several institutions that train public health professionals (16-19). In addition, the number of publications on ethical issues in epidemiology have increased (20-23). Indeed, all these developments have likely contributed to the increasing recognition of epidemiology as a distinct profession (2, 12).

The focus of these developments (ethics guidelines, curricula, and publications) has often been on identifying and communicating ethical rules and duties and on controversial or still-evolving ethical precepts (for example, the extent to which epidemiologists should engage in public health advocacy) (24-26). Ethical problems, such as conflicts of interest and scientific misconduct, have also been dealt with (27-33). Less attention has been given to core values in epidemiology, even though an examination of core values may help clarify ethical precepts in epidemiology while highlighting positive aspects of professional ethics.

To identify and clarify basic scientific values in the field, I examine core values in epidemiology and public health as reflected in mission statements for public health institutions, preambles to ethics guidelines for epidemiologists, and results obtained from ethics surveys. Professional values are discussed in relation to an important controversy in contemporary epidemiology: whether epidemiology has failed to sustain its commitment to public health. Finally, I discuss future directions of ethics and values in epidemiology.

Core Values in Epidemiology

Core values are fundamental ethical and scientific precepts (i.e., basic scientific values) that are consistent with and provide support for the mission and purpose of the profession. In the case of epidemiology, the mission is to acquire new scientific information that can be used to maintain, enhance, and promote the public's health (9, 34-36). Widely held and accepted core values exist within the profession of epidemiology. Nevertheless, individual epidemiologists may hold different opinions about core values and the values in the profession may gradually change or evolve over time (36). Core values in epidemiology are closely related to core values in the broader field of public health. As Barry Levy explained in his American Public Health Association presidential address in November 1997, "Values define us as a group of public health professionals; values drew many of us into public health in the first place" (37).

Published accounts suggest that, like other scientists, epidemiologists accept ideals of free inquiry and the pursuit of knowledge and that they uphold values of improving the public's health by applying scientific knowledge (5, 22). The way in which these core values guide epidemiologic research and practice is shaped by societal values and by the personal values of individual epidemiologists. As Susser and colleagues noted, an examination of ethics in epidemiology is an examination of the way in which the values of science and its potential benefits to public health are balanced against the values of individuals and communities (5). Other values within the profession that may be less fundamental but nevertheless important (for example, the value of establishing partnerships between academic and public health practice institutions) and epidemiologic duties and virtues (for example, the obligation that epidemiologists have to respect the autonomy of persons) further shape the influence of core values.

Core values can be distinguished from duties and ethical rules, which are more specific and tied to specific contexts (for example, the rule that research protocols involving human subjects should be submitted for ethical review by an institutional review board) (11, 38). Duties are those obligations epidemiologists hold to various parties, such as subjects, society, funding sources, employers, and colleagues (7, 11). Core values can also be distinguished from epidemiologic virtues that are often aspirational and grounded in professional character (for example, truth-telling, objectivity, and scientific excellence) (11, 39). Whereas epidemiologic values are not based in any particular moral theory, virtues are an important aspect of virtue ethics, a moral theory that emphasizes the character and moral motivation of the agent (person) rather than the actions taken by the person (39, 40).

Our understanding of core values and specific ethical rules and duties in epidemiology is shaped by contemporary discussions about ethical issues arising in biomedical research, such as issues arising in genetics research, how best to protect participants in placebo-controlled trials, and guidelines for conducting studies in developing countries (15, 41-43).

Epidemiologic values reflected in mission statements

Core values and other values in the profession are reflected in mission statements that have been drafted by an increasing number of epidemiology professional societies. For example, the mission statement of the American College of Epidemiology states that it is a professional organization that serves the interests of its members (i.e., epidemiologists) through sponsorship of scientific meetings, publications, and educational activities; it recognizes outstanding contributions to the field and advocates for issues pertinent to epidemiology (44). Thus, the college highlights the value of disseminating and sharing scientific information, providing continuing professional education, promoting scientific excellence, and advancing the profession. The mission statement of the International Society for Environmental Epidemiology states that the society provides a forum for discussing problems unique to the study of health and the environment. With membership open to environmental epidemiologists and other scientists worldwide, the society provides a variety of forums for discussions, critical reviews, collaborations, and education on issues of environmental exposures and their human health effects (45). These activities include annual meetings; newsletters; workshops; and liaisons with academic, governmental, inter-governmental, non-profit, and business institutions. Thus, in addition to the dissemination of scientific information and continuing professional education, the society upholds the value of international and interdisciplinary scientific collaboration and links with stakeholders outside the profession.

Epidemiology values are also reflected in statements drafted for public health institutions. For example, the U.S. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) statement of core values emphasizes the need for CDC employees to act decisively and compassionately in service to people’s health and to ensure that CDC research and services are based on sound science and meet genuine public needs (46). Respect for persons, cultural diversity, honesty, scientific integrity, and professional excellence are also emphasized in the statement. The CDC has employees from many disciplines, including epidemiology, the basic sciences, and other public health professions. The National Institutes of Health, a federal biomedical research institution in the United States, also has a multidisciplinary workforce. Its mission statement emphasizes science in pursuit of fundamental knowledge about the nature and behavior of living systems and the application of that knowledge to extend healthy life and reduce the burdens of illness and disability (47). The goals include creative discoveries and innovative research strategies; their application to protect and improve health; and scientific integrity, public accountability, and social responsibility in the conduct of science.

Many schools of public health (which include epidemiology training programs) have developed mission statements. The goals of the University of Texas at Houston School of Public Health, for example, emphasize education, research, community service, and the importance of public health values (table 1) (48). Public health practice, public health research, and service to local, state, national, and international agencies and communities are highlighted in the mission statement as well.

Epidemiologic values reflected in ethics guidelines

A number of sets of ethics guidelines for epidemiologists have been proposed (6-9). Guidelines drafted by the International Epidemiological Association include a preamble defining the purpose of epidemiology; a statement of core values in epidemiology; a summary of basic principles of biomedical ethics; and various sections outlining the obligations of epidemiologists to individuals, communities, colleagues, employers and funding agencies, and the profession (6). The guidelines state that "We who practice epidemiology are concerned with the health of all population groups. Our role is to identify interventions likely to restore, maintain and improve health... As public health professionals, we have an obligation to communities..." (6). Other values are implicit in the discussion of professional obligations of epidemiologists. For example, the association’s draft guidelines indicate that epidemiology is primarily concerned with providing service to communities and that epidemiologists are frequently drawn to the problems of disempowered communities. Cultural variations in values are also discussed in the guidelines.

Ethics guidelines proposed by the Industrial Epidemiology Forum provide an account of the obligations of epidemiologists to research subjects, society, employers and funding agencies, and colleagues (7). Although the guidelines are written in the form of professional obligations or duties, they do provide some information about core values in the field. For example, the accompanying commentary states that "The principles in these guidelines presume that there is no absolute right to scientific investigation even if scientific knowledge stands to be advanced appreciably. The advancement of knowledge is a worthy pursuit, but it is not so valuable as to provide a sufficient justification in all cases for overriding competing values such as privacy, confidentiality, and protection against risk" (7). Thus, the guidelines highlight the value that epidemiologists and society place on general ethical principles (e.g., avoiding harm, providing benefits, balancing benefits against risks, respecting personal autonomy, and protecting privacy and confidentiality).

The Council for International Organizations for Medical Sciences International Guidelines for Ethical Review of Epidemiological Studies address similar issues (8). They draw a distinction between epidemiologic research and routine practice and consider the problems associated with obtaining informed consent and respecting cultural differences in ethics and values in some epidemiologic studies. The guidelines note that "Ethical issues often arise as a result of conflict among competing sets of values, such as in the field of public health, the conflict between the rights of individuals, and the needs of communities" (8).

Ethics guidelines for environmental epidemiologists drafted by Soskolne and Light summarize the mission and core values of environmental epidemiology. They note that the mission of environmental epidemiology is to maintain, enhance, and promote health in communities worldwide by identifying or evaluating environmental hazards (9). Soskolne and Light also note that environmental epidemiologists contribute to scientific knowledge about environmental risks and environmentally induced diseases and that they protect public health at the local, regional, national, and global levels.

The Italian Epidemiological Association and the American College of Epidemiology are refining and updating ethics guidelines for epidemiologists. These documents are likely to further contribute to our understanding of ethics and values in epidemiology (17, 49).

Ethics guidelines for epidemiologists can be considered within the broader context of regional and international guidelines for biomedical researchers, which have also been periodically revised and updated (50, 51).

Epidemiologic values reflected in results from ethics surveys

Ethics surveys have provided information about the ethical interests and concerns of epidemiologists and about core values in the field. Surveys to date have targeted epidemiologists and other public health professionals, public health students, and institutions that train public health professionals (19, 52-55).

Soskolne and colleagues conducted an international ethics survey in 1994 among environmental epidemiologists (52). The participants were reached through mailings from the International Society for Environmental Epidemiology, the Italian Epidemiological Association, and the Global Environmental Epidemiology Network (managed by the Office of Global and Integrated Environmental Health of the World Health Organization, Geneva). The response rate was about 30 percent for the International Society for Environmental Epidemiology and the Italian Epidemiological Association and 19 percent for the Global Environmental Epidemiology Network. A total of 346 returned questionnaires were available for analysis. The survey focused on statements of ethical values and principles which were grouped into nine major areas. The greatest disagreement concerned the role of the environmental epidemiologist as a "dispassionate scientist" or a "passionate advocate"; other disagreement revolved around whether environmental epidemiology is an applied science or a basic science and whether environmental epidemiologists should be committed to influencing society in ways that maximize the likelihood of "health for all". Thus, the results suggest that different opinions among environmental epidemiologists exist about certain ethical precepts and professional obligations. The differences may reflect a lack of consensus about the mission of environmental epidemiology and core values in the field or, alternatively, a measurement problem (e.g., ambiguity in the wording of the questionnaire).

To obtain input from practicing epidemiologists on ethics guidelines, the American College of Epidemiology's Ethics and Standards of Practice Committee developed a questionnaire (53). The survey was conducted among a random sample of 300 North American members of the American College of Epidemiology, the Society for Epidemiologic Research, and the American Heart Association Council on Epidemiology and Prevention. The response rate was 88 percent (265 respondents). The majority of respondents agreed that any new ethics guidelines should address the goals and purposes of epidemiologic research which (according to questionnaire items for which there was good agreement) include "providing a rational basis for improving public health," "increasing scientific knowledge," and "establishing, guiding, changing public policy." There was less agreement among the respondents about the need for guidelines to address the "use of study results to advocate change in values or customs."

Professional Values and Epidemiology's Commitment to Public Health

The 1988 report The Future of Public Health by the Institute of Medicine observed that "public health professionals rely on expert knowledge derived from such areas as epidemiology and biostatistics to identify and deal with the health needs of whole populations. A central tenet of their professional ethic is commitment to use this knowledge to fulfill the public interest in reducing human suffering and enhancing the quality of life" (56). The report also noted that knowledge and values remain decisive elements in the shaping of public health practice. Similar sentiments were expressed by Krieger and Zierler who, as epidemiologists, share a vision of reducing human suffering by generating beneficial knowledge (57).

In the past decade, there has been extensive debate about whether epidemiology has lost its commitment to public health (58-62). Terris argued that as a result of a shift of epidemiologic research from health departments to schools of public health, epidemiology has withdrawn from the community (for example, fewer field studies and more secondary analyses of existing data) and concern with the methodology of data manipulation--rather than with the solution of disease problems--has grown (59). He noted "an orientation geared more to the goal of ‘publish or perish’ than to the goal of preventing disease and death" (59).

Some leading epidemiologists have criticized epidemiology subspecialties, such as clinical epidemiology and molecular epidemiology, because of a perceived lack of a population perspective and public health orientation. For example, Last argued against the uncritical enthusiasm with which clinical epidemiology has been embraced by many medical schools (63). He was concerned about a particular definition of epidemiology: the use of clinical experience to inform and guide decisions about the care of individual patients. Last argued that "such a narrow view of epidemiology would sadden the founders of the Epidemiological Society of London, most of whom were public health workers and saw epidemiology as a discipline that existed primarily to protect and promote the public health" (63). Of course, many clinical epidemiologists and epidemiologists in other subspecialties may uphold public health values (36).

Susser and Susser called for a return to public health values and for a paradigm shift from the current emphasis on individual risk factors for disease to a new ecological approach ("eco-epidemiology") that encompasses many levels of organization, including molecular, individual, and societal (61, 62). Gori observed that the two approaches (eco-epidemiology and the present paradigm, which emphasizes individual risk factors for disease) are complementary rather than opposed (64). In a commentary about "black box epidemiology," Weed argued that epidemiologists need a common set of values and that they lack consensus about their obligation to public health (65). He concluded that epidemiologists should embrace a systems theory approach.

Although epidemiologists remain divided about the need for a new scientific paradigm in their field, the debate has drawn attention to the need for a sustained epidemiologic commitment to public health. To some commentators, present efforts in epidemiology to address public health problems are insufficient. Echoing concerns by others (57-62), Pearce and McKinlay recently argued that epidemiologists should pay more attention to the real determinants of health at the upstream population level (including socioeconomic, cultural, and political factors), address the most important public health questions, and use appropriate methods to address these questions (66). Such scientific arguments are founded in social concerns and in core values in epidemiology and public health.

Ethics, Values, and Future Directions in Epidemiology

One future direction in epidemiology is likely to be the further development of curricula on public health ethics for epidemiology graduate students, including coursework on the ethics of epidemiologic research and practice (16-19, 55, 67). The Council on Education for Public Health criteria for graduate schools of public health in the United States emphasize public health values, concepts, and ethics, but do not currently require ethics instruction. Courses on public health ethics provide students with the conceptual abilities and decision-making skills they need to deal successfully with ethical issues in their own research and practice (18). The cognitive aspects of ethics that can be taught include the identification of the ethical commitments of epidemiologic research and practice, the application of concepts and methods for ethical decision-making to actual cases, and critical reflection about personal values and obligations as a public health professional (18, 39). Small group discussion of ethics cases, including important historical cases such as the Tuskegee Syphilis Study, is an important part of such coursework (54). Core values in epidemiology and public health are often transmitted informally through informal teaching and mentoring of students and fellows. Schools of public health and academic departments of epidemiology can be seen as communities with their own culture and subculture; students and fellows are taught what is valued in that culture and are provided opportunities to internalize the core values (68).

Future directions in epidemiology are also likely to include the development of mission statements, statements of core values, and ethics guidelines for epidemiology specialties, such as molecular epidemiology, reproductive and perinatal epidemiology, and public health practice (2). Such efforts contribute to the further recognition of epidemiology subspecialties as distinct subdisciplines while reinforcing their commitment to public health. Mission statements and statements of core values may also contribute to efforts to educate the public and stakeholders about the societal importance of epidemiology.

Another possible direction is the further incorporation of epidemiologic perspectives into policy statements and regulations that deal with the protection of human subjects, the privacy and confidentiality of medical records, and genetic testing (14, 15). For example, distinctions have not always been drawn between highly penetrant disease susceptibility genes and more common genetic polymorphisms in developing ethical rules for genetic testing carried out as part of research protocols (69).

Substantial attention has been given to issues surrounding the privacy and confidentiality of medical records, data sharing, and linkage of large databases for the purposes of health research (13, 14, 70). In view of recent legal and regulatory developments in these areas, and technological refinements such as increased use of health information systems and of the Internet (71, 72), epidemiologists are likely to continue to face professional challenges related to these important topics for the foreseeable future.

Finally, more attention will likely be given to ethics and values in public health practice and to ways to resolve conflicts between professional values and community values (73-75). The ethics of public health practice have often been neglected in the literature on ethics and epidemiology compared with issues that arise in epidemiologic research, but recent articles and presentations at scientific meetings suggest that increasing attention is being devoted to these important issues.

References

1. Coughlin SS. Historical foundations. In: Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996:5-23.

2. Coughlin SS. Advancing professional ethics in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Biostat 1996;1:71-7.

3. Gordis L, Gold E, Seltser R. Privacy protection in epidemiologic and medical research: a challenge and a responsibility. Am J Epidemiol 1977;105:163-8.

4. Cann CI, Rothman KJ. IRBs and epidemiologic research: how inappropriate restrictions hamper studies. IRB 1984;6:5-7.

5. Susser M, Stein Z, Kline J. Ethics in epidemiology. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 1978;437:128-41.

6. International Epidemiological Association. Ethical guidelines for epidemiologists (draft). In: Epidemiology section newsletter. Washington, DC: American Public Health Association, Winter 1990.

7. Beauchamp TL, Cook RR, Fayerweather WE, et al. Ethical guidelines for epidemiologists. J Clin Epidemiol 1991;44:151S-69S.

8. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies. Law Med Health Care 1991;19:247-58.

9. Soskolne CL, Light A. Toward ethics guidelines for environmental epidemiologists. Total Environ 1996;184:137-47.

10. Last J. Professional standards of conduct for epidemiologists. In: Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996:53-75.

11. Beauchamp TL. Moral foundations. In: Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and Epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996:24-52.

12. Coughlin SS. On the role of ethics committees in epidemiology professional societies. Am J Epidemiol 1997;146;209-13.

13. Hogue CJR. Ethical issues in sharing epidemiologic data. J Clin Epidemiol 1991;44(Suppl I);103S-7S.

14. American College of Epidemiology. Draft policy statement on privacy of medical records. Epidemiol Monitor 1998;19:9-11.

15. Clayton EW, Steinberg KK, Khoury MJ, et al. Informed consent for genetic research on stored tissue samples. JAMA 1995;274:1786-92.

16. Goodman KW, Prineas RJ. Toward an ethics curriculum in epidemiology. In: Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996:290-303.

17. Coughlin SS, Etheredge GD. On the need for ethics curricula in epidemiology. Epidemiology 1995;6:566-7.

18. Coughlin SS. Model curricula in public health ethics. Am J Prev Med 1996;12:247-51.

19. Rossignol AM, Goodmonson S. Are ethical topics in epidemiology included in the graduate epidemiology curricula? Am J Epidemiol 1996;142:1265-8.

20. Fayerweather WE, Higginson J, Beauchamp TL, eds. Industrial Epidemiology Forum’s Conference on Ethics in Epidemiology. J Clin Epidemiol 1991;44(Suppl I).

21. Coughlin SS, ed. Ethics in epidemiology and clinical research: annotated readings. Newton, MA: Epidemiology Resources Inc., 1995.

22. Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996.

23. Soskolne CL, Bertollini R, eds. Ethical and philosophical issues in environmental epidemiology. Proceedings of a WHO/ISEE International Workshop, 16-18 September, 1994, Research Triangle Park, North Carolina, USA. Science Total Environ 1996;184.

24. Weed DL. Science, ethics guidelines, and advocacy in epidemiology. Ann Epidemiol 1994;4:166-71.

25. Rothman KJ, Poole C. Science and policy making (editorial). Am J Public Health 1985;75:340-1.

26. Krieger N. Questioning epidemiology: objectivity, advocacy, and socially responsible science. Am J Public Health 1999;89:1151-61.

27. Soskolne CL. Epidemiological research, interest groups and the review process. J Public Health Policy 1985;7:173-84.

28. Rothman KJ. Conflict of interest: the new McCarthyism in science. JAMA 1993;269:2782-4.

29. Rothman KJ, Cann CI. Judging words rather than authors (editorial). Epidemiology 1997;8:223-5.

30. Manson JE. Adventures in scientific discourse. Epidemiology 1997;8:324-6.

31. Soskolne CL, ed. Proceedings of the symposium on ethics and law in environmental epidemiology. J Exp Anal Environ Epidemiol 1993;3(Suppl 1):243-319.

32. Soskolne CL, MacFarlane DK. Scientific misconduct in epidemiologic research. In: Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996:274-89.

33. Weed DL. Preventing scientific misconduct. Am J Public Health 1998;88:125-9.

34. Gellermann W, Frankel MS, Ladenson RF. Values and ethics in organization and human systems development. Responding to dilemmas in professional life. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass, 1990.

35. Flores A, ed. Professional ideals. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publication Company, 1988.

36. Coughlin SS. Scientific paradigms in epidemiology and professional values. Epidemiology 1998;9:578-80.

37. Levy BS. Creating the future of public health: values, vision, and leadership. Am J Public Health 1998;88:188-92.

38. Weed DL. Epistemology and ethics in epidemiology. In: Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds. Ethics and epidemiology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1996:76-94.

39. Weed DL, McKeown RE. Epidemiology and virtue ethics. Int J Epidemiol 1998;27:343-9.

40. Pellegrino ED. Toward a virtue-based normative ethics for the health professions. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 1995;5:253-77.

41. Annas GJ, Elias S. Gene Mapping: Using Law and Ethics as Guides. New York: Oxford University Press, 1992.

42. Faden R, Kass N. HIV research, ethics, and the developing world (editorial). Am J Public Health 1998;88:548-50.

43. Perinatal HIV Intervention Research in Developing Countries Workshop Participants. Consensus statement: science, ethics, and the future of research into maternal infant transmission of HIV-1. Lancet 1999;353:832-5.

44. American College of Epidemiology history [http://www.amcollepi.org/history.html].

45. International Society for Environmental Epidemiology mission and philosophy [http://www.medualberta.ca/PHS/ISEE/frames/ mission.htm].

46. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention core values [http://www.cdc.gov/ aboutcdc.htm#mission].

47. National Institutes of Health Overview. NIH Almanac 1997 [http://www.nih.gov/ welcome/almanac97/overview.htm].

48. University of Texas at Houston School of Public Health statement of mission [http://www.sph.uth.tmc.edu/www/cat/mission.HTM].

49. Weed DL, Coughlin SS. New ethics guidelines for epidemiology: background and rationale. Ann Epidemiol 1999;9:277-80.

50. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects. Geneva: CIOMS, 1993.

51. Declaration of Helsinki-nothing to declare? (editorial). Lancet 1999;353:1285.

52. Soskolne CL, Jhangri GS, Hunter B, et al. Interim report on the Joint International Society for Environmental Epidemiology (ISEE)--Global Environmental Epidemiology Network (GEENET) ethics survey. Sci Total Environ 1996;184:5-11.

53. Prineas RJ, Goodman K, Soskolne CL, et al. Findings from the American College of Epidemiology ethics survey on the need for ethics guidelines for epidemiologists. Ann Epidemiol 1998;8:482-9.

54. Coughlin SS, Etheredge GD, Metayer C, et al. Remember Tuskegee: public health student knowledge of the ethical significance of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. Am J Prev Med 1996;12:242-6.

55. Coughlin SS, Katz WH, Mattison DR. Ethics instruction at schools of public health in the United States. Am J Public Health 1999;89:768-70.

56. Committee for the Study of the Future of Public Health, Institute of Medicine. The future of public health. Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1988.

57. Krieger N, Zierler S. What explains the public’s health? A call for epidemiologic theory. Epidemiology 1996;7:107-9.

58. Morris JN. Modern epidemiology? J Epidemiol Community Health 1988;42:100.

59. Terris M. The Society for Epidemiologic Research (SER) and the future of epidemiology. Am J Epidemiol 1992;136:909-15.

60. Pearce N. Traditional epidemiology, modern epidemiology, and public health. Am J Public Health 1996;86:678-83.

61. Susser M, Susser E. Choosing a future for epidemiology. I. Eras and paradigms. Am J Public Health 1996;86:668-73.

62. Susser M, Susser E. Choosing a future for epidemiology. II. From black box to Chinese boxes and eco-epidemiology. Am J Public Health 1996;86:674-7.

63. Last JM. What is "clinical epidemiology?" J Public Health Policy 1988;9:159-63.

64. Gori GB. Epidemiology and public health: is a new paradigm needed or a new ethic? J Clin Epidemiol 1998;51:637-41.

65. Weed DL. Beyond black box epidemiology. Am J Public Health 1998;88:12-4.

66. Pearce N, McKinlay JB. Back to the future in epidemiology and public health: response to Dr. Gori. J Clin Epidemiol 1998;51:643-6.

67. Coughlin SS, Soskolne CL, Goodman KW. Case studies in public health ethics. Washington, DC: American Public Health Association, 1997.

68. Bloom SW. Reform without change? Look beyond the curriculum (editorial). Am J Public Health 1995;85:907-8.

69. Hunter D, Caporaso N. Informed consent in epidemiologic studies involving genetic markers. Epidemiology 1997;8:596-9.

70. "DHHS preparing to promulgate privacy regulations if Congress fails to pass new privacy law." Epidemiology Monitor 1999;7-8.

71. Campbell SG, Gibby GL, Collingwood S. The Internet and electronic transmission of medical records. J Clin Monitoring 1997;13:325-34.

72. Barrows RC, Clayton PD. Privacy, confidentiality, and electronic medical records. J Am Med Informatics Assoc 1996;3:139-48.

73. Coughlin SS. Ethics in epidemiology and public health practice. In: Coughlin SS. Epidemiology and public health practice: collected works. Columbus, GA: Quill Publications, 1997:9-26.

74. Soskolne CL. Rationalizing professional conduct: ethics in disease control. Public Health Rev 1991;19:311-21.

75. Wartenberg D. Ethics in community-based environmental epidemiology and public health practice: some considerations. Sci Total Environ 1996;184:109-12.

 

Table 1. University of Texas at Houston School of Public Health Mission and Goals1

The mission of the school is to improve and sustain the health of people by providing the highest quality graduate education, research, and community service for Texas, the nation, and internationally.

The school provides the citizens of Texas the opportunity for quality graduate education in the basic disciplines and practices of public health, extends knowledge of these disciplines, and assists public health practitioners. The mission emphasizes:

Education - The school’s first responsibility is to provide present and future practitioners, teachers, and scientists the highest quality graduate education in the theory and practice of public health. Its educational philosophy is based on the premise that education is a lifelong process and that, while the school offers resources and guidance, the fundamental responsibility for each person’s education resides with the individual, with guidance and support of the faculty. The school teaches public health values and a diversity of skills in the physical, biological, behavioral, and analytic sciences needed by public health practitioners today. The school is committed to maintaining a broad perspective of health, disease, and the health care system.

Research - The school is committed to the pursuit of knowledge which enhances both the theory and practice of public health. Faculty support and engage in research directed toward such activities as health promotion, environmental health, disease control, and health care delivery.

Community Service - The faculty seek to provide service to local, state, national and international health agencies that is consistent with the school’s instructional and research commitments. The school develops public policy, contributes to the activities of these agencies, and enhances the well-being of the public.

1UT-Houston School of Public Health statement of mission